I just finished reading E.O. Wilson's The Social Conquest of Earth. Written as it was for an educated yet not academically minded audience it is hardly surprising that I didn't learn much new from the book. Nevertheless, it should serve as a handy reference for teaching in the future and I found it refreshing to see the multi-level selection approach so forcefully promoted even if, in some places, I believe Wilson overstated the case. Unfortunately, Wilson makes a number of unwarranted and poorly informed attacks against religion. In the future, I may take each of these in turn. For the moment, however, I'd like to comment on one in particular since it touches on my own research.
Wilson makes a number of impassioned pleas toward the end of the book about the critical juncture the human species finds itself at. As might be expected from a biologist, his loudest cries are for the state of the environment:
Sure one moral precept we can agree on is to stop destroying our birthplace, the only home humanity will ever have.
That's certainly a moral precept I can agree on and one that I feel rather strongly about as well. However, Wilson goes on to say:
It will be useful in taking a second look at science and religion to understand the true nature of the search for objective truth. Science is not just another enterprise like medicine or engineering or theology. It is the wellspring of all the knowledge we have of the real world that can be tested and fitted into preexisting knowledge. It is the arsenal of technologies and inferential mathematics needed to distinguish the true from the false. It formulates the principles and formulas that tie all this knowledge together. Science belongs to everybody. Its constituent parts can be challenged by anybody in the world who has sufficient information to do so. It is not just "another way of knowing" as often claimed, making it coequal with religious faith. The conflict between scientific knowledge and the teachings of organized religions is irreconcilable. The chasm will continue to widen and cause no end of trouble as long as religious leaders go on making unsupportable claims about supernatural causes of reality.
To put this into better perspective, Wilson just a few paragraphs earlier said:
Why, then, is it wise openly to question the myths and gods of organized religion? Because they are stultifying and divisive. Because each is just one version of a competing multitude of scenarios that possibly can be true. Because they encourage ignorance, distract people from recognizing problems of the real world, and often lead them in wrong directions into disastrous actions.
So now we get to the heart of my objection. As I read it, Wilson is essentially trying to lay the blame for environmental degradation at the feet of religion. Moreover, he suggests that the only antidote to the destructive nature of religion's superstition is the cold rationality of the scientific enterprise.
This is particularly obnoxious to me because I have been working for the past year and a half on a project with some of Lin Ostrom's students that looks specifically at the relationship between religion and the management of natural resources. We still have two more cases to code before we begin our analysis. Nevertheless, it is clear from the 48 cases that we've looked at so far that religion has traditionally had extremely important roles to play in the sustainable use of resources. For instance, religion often serves to define the physical boundaries of resources and marks those who are allowed to use them. Religion serves monitoring functions and imposes sanctions for those who break the rules. It also is an important source of perceived benefits that encourage users to cooperate with others. Religion provides opportunities for leadership, repositories of local knowledge, calendars to coordinate cooperative efforts and avenues for the establishment and maintenance of social capital. To say that religion in this context is "stultifying and divisive" is plain and simply wrong. It is both highly innovative and creative and it leads to greater cooperation for an enterprise that is notoriously difficult.
Now, I can hear the objections already that religion is hardly necessary to provide these services. This is a fair point. Indeed, many groups do use secular alternatives to great effect. Furthermore, many groups that we've studied employ a mixture of religious and secular mechanisms to govern their resources sustainably. Nevertheless, the fact that religion is providing these vital functions should alone be enough to give us pause about actively working to undermine them. At least it should give us pause if our primary goal is really better stewardship of the planet. Religious means of encoding culturally important information may not be rational in the sense that Wilson and others understand that term. They certainly weren't arrived at through a deliberate process of empirical research checked through peer review. For that matter they often probably didn't arise as deliberate conservation efforts in the first place. Many of them, however, have been in use for centuries and, as such, have been subjected to generations of cultural evolution which has produced finely tuned institutions, exquisitely sensitive to local environmental contexts. Surely if biologists can't place any credence on supernatural entities and superstitious articulations of the way the world works they can at least give some respect for systems refined through natural selection!
Finally, religion is hardly unique in its ability "to distract people from recognizing problems of the real world," nor is it alone in leading "them in wrong directions into disastrous actions." Time and again we have found cases in our work where the leading cause of the breakdown in sustainable resource management by user groups can be traced to either the privatization of the resource in question or, more often, to the usurpation of local user rights through nationalization. In this latter case, national governments take over control of resources, eliminating any semblance of local autonomy and denying local users any collective choice rights to determine the rules they are expected to follow. The results of this kind of policy are almost universally disastrous, leading to rapid environmental degradation.
And where did these policy notions come from? It was decidedly not from the world's religions. Rather, it came from western scientists and scholars whose thinking was summarized so concisely and compellingly in Hardin's Tragedy of the Commons. This represents policy based on rational thought and enjoying strong empirical support from modeling studies and laboratory experiments. In short, it represents exactly the sort of approach that Wilson touts as being inherently superior to the "unsupportable claims" of religious leaders. It also happens to be completely and disastrously wrong as Elinor Ostrom's work has shown, work for which she earned a Nobel Prize. I only hope that the damage caused by such superior, rational thinking can be repaired before it's too late for us all.
This is a place for the members of the Wilson lab to support and challenge one another as they develop their projects.
Saturday, August 25, 2012
Thursday, August 23, 2012
Energy Rate Density, Fitness and Reproduction
As you (Ian and Yasha) know I have been struggling with the
idea of differences between absolute and relative fitness. I just typed out something that just occurred to me. Let me know what you think.
Not all traits/behavior may contribute to reproductive
success. If we consider reproduction as a special case, then those traits
become relevant that contribute to reproductive success as they can get
selected and evolve.
If reproduction does not occur in a system, then
those traits will evolve (by means that do not specifically require
reproduction/heredity) that contribute to...well just living and increasing/maintaining the
bearers free energy rate density (Chaisson, 2011).
If the above has some meaning then bringing together the two
ideas of "reproduction is a special case" and "is there a
difference between absolute and relative fitness" leads you to this
conclusion, traits that contribute to increasing free energy rate density can
be broken down into two types those that rely on reproduction and thus
contribute to increasing reproductive fitness and those that do not contribute
to in any conceivable way to increasing reproductive fitness.
In the second scenario those traits that rely on
reproduction and contribute to a increase in reproductive fitness are traits
that increase relative fitness of an organism in a population over time.
The first scenario describes contribution of a trait to
absolute fitness, where a trait might not have anything to do with reproduction
or reproductive success. It just contributes to maximizing free energy rate
density..just living.
Chaisson, E. J.
(2011). Energy rate density as a complexity metric and evolutionary driver. Complexity,
16(3), 27–40. doi:10.1002/cplx.20323
Wednesday, August 22, 2012
The meaning of the adaptation to tolerate lactose.
The question
that is most often asked about lactose tolerance is that if drinking milk is an
evolutionary adaptation shouldn't we continue to reap its fitness benefits? Although this question may be frowned upon by individuals who study evolutionary biology it is an important question to answer as it addresses the issues that are important to understanding of evolution; adaptation and natural selection.
I will
explore this question in two parts first I will explain the adaptation of
lactose tolerance and then I will explore how natural selection effects life history evolution.
Is Lactose tolerance an adaptation?
Lactose
tolerance occurs due to a genetic mutation(s) that confers an ability to digest
lactose from milk. Lactose tolerance appeared as a fortuitous mutation, yet it got
selected as a result of the fitness benefits it conferred; it had beneficial
effects on the adaptedness (absolute fitness) of individual humans within an
environmental context. Natural selection then occurred as a result of
differences in adaptedness of individuals within a specific population; i.e.
some individuals could drink milk into adulthood whereas others couldn’t. Over
time, those individuals that could drink milk into adulthood survived and
reproduced at relatively higher rate than those who could not. Over many
generations, through the process of
adaptation the trait for digesting lactose became adaptive within a spatio-temporal context.
Even though
the trait arose as a fortuitous mutation it became
adaptive as it created differences in absolute fitness and set stage for
natural selection to occur. Lactose tolerance gene was definitely an adaptation
to milk drinking in the spatio-temporal context it evolved in; must this mean
that this trait is as adaptive today as it was in our past? Does a trait’s
noble legacy justify its credentials in the present? This may not always be
true and the answer depends on the differences between past and present and the
nature of life history evolution.
It is
important at this point to understand that all adaptations have three aspects.
a)
Historical; an adaptive trait is present today in an organism because it
provided fitness benefits to its bearers and there was a selection for the adaptive trait.
b) Spatial:
An adaptive trait is a specific solution to a problem posed by a feature of a
given environment.
c)
Eventual: Adaptive traits have the ability to confer (present and future)
fitness benefits to its bearers.
Whether or
not an adaptive trait persists through time depends on a number of factors; the
environment being the most critical of them. If there are minimal changes in
the environment (over evolutionary time) such that the plasticity allows the
trait to persist, then the trait remains a legible solution to the problems
posed by the environment. On the contrary, if the environment has changed substantially enough so that the
plasticity of the trait does not buffer the changes, then the trait finds
itself in uncharted waters. Sober pointed out in “The Nature of Selection” that
“the benefits that account for a traits fixation need not persist into the
present. “The benefits that account for a traits fixation” are governed by the
environment (Sober, 1993).
If one
considers just the historical aspect of an adaptive trait then “a trait can be
an adaptation for performing some task, even though performing that task in the
present environment confers no benefit” (Sober, 1993).
This
statement can be misunderstood as the reader might comprehend that a traits noble
legacy justifies it present credentials. An adaptive trait remains an
adaptation no matter what happens. I would like to clarify what I think Sober
meant for the reader to read between the lines; an adaptive trait remains an
adaptive trait, retrospectively. A
trait is an adaptation just because it was
an adaptation in the spatial context
it evolved. The trait conferred fitness benefits to its eventual bearers.
The trait will still be called adaptive; the process which shaped the trait
will still be called adaptation, but retrospectively. Whether an adaptive
trait is adaptive today depends on the environmental context of the trait. If
the environment is substantially different from the environment in which the
trait evolved and became adaptive then the trait may not confer any fitness
benefits (Remember that the trait is still adaptive but…you guessed
it…retrospectively). If the environment changes, the trait remains adaptive
looking at the past; whether the trait still persists as an adaptation in the
future is another issue altogether.
There are
three scenarios a trait may experience if the environment changes; a) the trait
may not confer any fitness benefits, i.e. remain neutral and adaptive
retrospectively; b) the trait may happen to confer fitness benefits, persist
being adaptive; and c) the trait confers negative fitness benefits and become maladaptive.
Going back
to the adaptive trait of Lactose tolerance, we can either say that Lactose
tolerance was an adaptation in the
spatio-temporal context that favored its prevalence or lactose tolerance is an adaptation retrospectively. Both
statements are correct as long as you understand the definition of an
adaptation. The question therefore is not whether lactose tolerance is an
adaptation. It most definitely is! The question is whether lactose tolerance is
an adaptation in today’s environmental context?
In the arid
climates of Middle and Near east dairy has been suggested to be the major
source of clean uncontaminated water (Cook & Al-Torki, 1975). The individuals that could drink milk into
adulthood happened to have higher relative fitness than those who could not. In
northern Europe dairy was the source of calcium, this must have been crucial in
place where there is very little sunlight (Flatz & Rotthauwe, 1973).
Thus the
trait was selected and as the populations of individuals travelled across the
world the trait travelled with them. In certain places the trait might have
been still adaptive; yet, in other places the adaptive trait might have lost
its relevant environmental context. Rehydration through consumption of dairy is
not a necessity when you live next to a river, for example.
Thus we can
say that in certain populations in the past (and today) the adaptive trait of
lactose tolerance lost its relevance, as it could not confer fitness benefits.
It is lingering in our gene pool as a consequence of fitness benefits it
conferred to its bearers in their environmental
context. Those fitness benefits are not relevant in those populations whose
environmental context has changed. Thus lactose tolerance does not remain an
adaptation in those populations; however, that does not take away the adaptive
legacy of the trait. The trait has become a not-so-benign ghost of Christmas
past.
Lactose Tolerance is a mal-adaptation
Now that I
have established that a trait can lose its adaptive significance in a changed environmental context I will try
to make the case that this trait is not just a neutral adaptation but has the
potential to be transformed into a mal-adaptation in todays environmental
context. Lactose tolerance and the resultant consumption of milk have been
linked to many chronic diseases of the western civilization. Chronic
consumption of milk has been associated primarily with auto-immune diseases
(Type 1 Diabetes, Rheumatoid Arthritis, and Multiple Sclerosis) (Elliott, Harris, Hill, Bibby, & Wasmuth, 1999; Malosse, Perron,
Sasco, & Seigneurin, 1992), consumption of dairy has also been correlated
to prostate cancer and insulin resistance (Pereira et al., 2002; Qin et al., 2004). The ghost-adaptation of lactose tolerance is making
us realize the necessity of changing our ways (I couldn’t help myself there ).
Lactose tolerance today is a mal-adaptation
as the trait was previously selected for by
natural selection, lost its relevance, and now is becoming a crucial factor in
the development of chronic diseases.
Natural Selection and Life History Evolution
There is
another important aspect to the “adaptation” of consuming dairy into adulthood.
It is centered on the workings of natural selection.
Natural
selection operates most quickly on traits and behaviors that are expressed
during the reproductive years of the life cycle. A trait that hampers
reproductive ability in the young will be quickly eliminated from the
population. A trait that is expressed in the in the older individuals will be
removed much more slowly. As lactose tolerance was beneficial for individuals
within a certain environmental context it got selected irrespective of the
long-term effect it caused.
The
following table may help to explain which traits get naturally selected. Traits
and adaptations may have in all four aspects: a) short term benefit, b) short
term cost, c) long term benefit, and d) long term cost
Traits that
have short (during reproductive years) and long term benefits (longevity) will
get naturally selected so will traits that have short term benefit and a long
term cost. Traits with short term cost will get weeded out if they negatively affect
an organisms’ fit with the environment. Lactose tolerance, in todays changed environmental contexts falls
into the category of traits that have short term benefit and long term cost.
Summary
Thus, the
question, “if lactose tolerance is an adaptation shouldn’t we continue to drink
milk?” has two sub-questions. First, is lactose tolerance an adaptation in
todays environmental context? And second aspect deals with nature of life
history evolution and natural selection. The answer to the first question tell
us that lactose tolerance is does not remain an adaptation in a changed environmental context, moreover
it has become a mal-adaptation due to enabling of chronic consumption of milk.
Dairy consumption has been correlated locally as well as globally with many diseases
of civilization. The answer to the second question addresses the issue that a
trait that confers fitness benefits in reproductive life will tend to get
selected even though it has long term costs.
Summary
Statement: Lactose tolerance is a retrospective adaptation that has the
potential to become mal-adaptive in a changed environmental context.
References
Cook, G. C., & Al-Torki, M. T. (1975). High intestinal lactase
concentrations in adult Arbs in Saudi Arabia. British Medical Journal, 3(5976),
135–136.
Elliott, R.
B., Harris, D. P., Hill, J. P., Bibby, N. J., & Wasmuth, H. E. (1999). Type
I (insulin-dependent) diabetes mellitus and cow milk: casein variant
consumption. Diabetologia, 42(3), 292–296.
Flatz, G.,
& Rotthauwe, H. W. (1973). Lactose nutrition and natural selection. The
Lancet, 302(7820), 76–77.
Malosse,
D., Perron, H., Sasco, A., & Seigneurin, J. M. (1992). Correlation between
milk and dairy product consumption and multiple sclerosis prevalence: a
worldwide study. Neuroepidemiology, 11(4-6), 304–312.
Pereira, M.
A., Jacobs Jr, D. R., Van Horn, L., Slattery, M. L., Kartashov, A. I., &
Ludwig, D. S. (2002).
Dairy consumption, obesity, and the insulin resistance
syndrome in young adults. JAMA: the journal of the American Medical
Association, 287(16), 2081–2089.
Qin, L.-Q.,
Xu, J.-Y., Wang, P.-Y., Kaneko, T., Hoshi, K., & Sato, A. (2004). Milk
Consumption Is a Risk Factor for Prostate Cancer: Meta-Analysis of Case-Control
Studies. Nutrition and Cancer, 48(1), 22–27.
doi:10.1207/s15327914nc4801_4
Sober, E.
(1993). The nature of selection: evolutionary theory in philosophical focus.
University of Chicago Press. Retrieved from
http://books.google.com/books?hl=en&lr=&id=6bLZQzDd0f4C&oi=fnd&pg=PR9&dq=nature+of+selection&ots=NqnNZ0V_xs&sig=yt2t6n05ZurIb8JigyFXDenPRVE
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)